§5. The Negative Interpretation
Tải bản đầy đủ - 0trang
:
. I interpret the text as follows: if the promisee were to apply the CIprocedure to the maxim from which the deceitful promisor acts, the promisee would reject it, just as the promisor would also reject it were the promisor to follow that procedure. When Kant speaks of lack of agreement (in
the second sentence of II: [–]), he means that the promisor’s maxim
cannot be endorsed by the promisee. Thus if promisor and promisee both
act from maxims that pass the CI-procedure, they would accept and reject
the same maxims, and both would contain in their persons (and in this
sense endorse) each other’s (permissible) ends.
If this reading is correct, we can see why in II: (–) Kant says
that:
So act in relation to every reasonable and rational being (both yourself
and others) that that being may at the same time count in your maxim
as an end in itself
is fundamentally the same as:
Act on a maxim which at the same time contains in itself its own
universal validity for every reasonable and rational being.
Here it is the maxim that contains in itself (in sich enhaălt) its own validity,
which must mean that every reasonable and rational person who applies
the CI-procedure correctly will see that the maxim passes, and therefore
that all can endorse it.
. This interpretation may seem a bit thin, even disappointing. Surely
Kant means more than this! Indeed he does in the positive interpretation
for the duties of virtue. But the negative interpretation fits the important
case of the duties of justice. That Kant has these duties in mind in the
promising example is shown by his saying that the requirement that others
must be able to contain in their person the end of our action is even
more plainly violated in attempts on the freedom and property of others
(the rights of man). For in these cases, it is clear that we intend to treat
others merely as means: we know perfectly well that they cannot endorse
our end; we clearly fail to treat them as ends against which we should
never act.
[ ]
Of course, the duties of virtue also satisfy this interpretation, since others
can endorse the maxims of ends from which we act when we fulfill our
duties of virtue. The difference is that with those duties we also promote
the ends enjoined by those maxims: stated in a summary way, we cultivate
our own moral and natural perfection and further the happiness of others.
Whereas the duties of justice can be met simply by acting within the limits
established by a just system of law, and even though we pursue only our
own interests and are indifferent to those of others. The duties of justice
require no more than the mutual endorsability of the maxims governing
our outer actions.
To conclude: humanity in us is simply our powers of reason and
thought, and of moral judgment and sensibility. To treat persons as ends
in matters of justice—to treat humanity in them as an end—and never as
means only is to conduct ourselves in ways that are publicly justifiable to
their and our common human reason, and of offering such justifications as
the occasion demands. If, further, we care for justice (we count respecting
the right of persons as our end and widen our concept of duty beyond what
is due [MdS :f.]), then we act from what Kant calls the obligation of
virtue (MdS :). We take a pure practical interest in associating with
others in ways that they can publicly endorse. That is a very important
idea.2
. We have yet to consider the first example of suicide (II: []). Does
the negative interpretation apply to it? Let’s look at the fuller statement
Kant gives in MdS :f. There he writes:
Man cannot renounce his personality as long as he is a subject of
duty, and hence so long as he lives. It is a contradiction that he should
have the moral title to withdraw from all obligation, that is freely to
act as if he needed no moral title for this action. To destroy the subject
of morality in one’s own person is to root out the existence of morality
2. The motivation of our desiring to associate with others in ways that they can publicly
endorse, or in ways that can be mutually justified, both to them and to us, is taken as a basic
assumption of T. M. Scanlon’s contractualism. See his “Contractualism and Utilitarianism,” in Utilitarianism and Beyond, ed. A. Sen and B. Williams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ),
pp. –.
[ ]
:
itself from the world, so far as this is in one’s power; and yet morality
is an end-in-itself. Thus to dispose of oneself as a mere means to an
arbitrary end [an end of natural inclination] is to abase humanity
in one’s own person (homo noumenon), which was yet entrusted to
man as being in the world of nature (homo phenomenon) for its preservation.
I don’t read this passage as saying that suicide is always wrong. Rather,
it says that a moral title for it is always needed, which cannot be given by
the ends wanted by natural inclination. The casuistical questions Kant lists
in this section imply that such a title can be given by conflicting grounds
of obligation (MdS :); for these may be at times stronger than the
ground not to take our life. Otherwise, the questions listed are not questions! Kant asks, for example, whether it is wrong of a commanding general
to carry poison so that if captured he can avoid being ransomed on conditions prejudicial to his country (a reference to Frederick the Great). While
Kant’s doctrine excludes suicide for reasons based solely on our natural
inclinations, it is not always forbidden whatever the reasons. What is required are very strong reasons based on obligatory ends, which may conflict
in particular circumstances.
The difficult passage in Gr II: (–) may also apply to suicide. Kant
says that a subject (person) that is capable of a good will cannot without
contradiction be subordinated to any other object. He is, I think, invoking
the priority of the value of a good will found at Gr I: (). When we take
our life for reasons based on natural inclinations, we subordinate our moral
powers to something of merely relative value; this, Kant may think, is a
contradiction in the order of values. This fits what Kant says about suicide
above in the Doctrine of Virtue.
There is, however, an important gap. We still lack an argument of the
appropriate kind relying solely on the CI-procedure for the prohibition
against suicide. What we can say, though, is that given such an argument,
it would then be true that suicide fits under the negative interpretation. It
would mean that humanity in us—our moral sensibility and powers of pure
practical reason—could not endorse our suicidal action if prompted by our
natural inclinations.
[ ]
§. The Positive Interpretation
. The meaning of the positive interpretation is now clear. We treat humanity in our own person and in the person of others as an end-in-itself in a
positive way by conscientiously promoting the obligatory ends specified by
the duties of virtue. Described summarily, we do this by striving to advance
our own perfection (moral and natural) and the happiness of others, where
this is specified by their permissible ends (MdS :; ). Assuming that the
duties of virtue are given by maxims of ends enjoined by the CI-procedure,
the second formulation does not add to the content of the moral law as
specified by the strict method (II: []). It gives another way to look at
the content of that law—its matter, as it were (II: []).
Read this way, the positive interpretation emphasizes that there are objective ends: those valid for all reasonable and rational persons in the sense
that every such person must count these ends as ends they are to advance.
Thus the moral law not only imposes limits on the means we may adopt
in the pursuit of ends as permitted by the duties of justice, but also directs
us to hold certain ends as obligatory. In a phrase: the moral law determines
elements of the matter, as well as determining the form, of pure will (MdS
:f.). This is important in connection with Kant’s account of freedom:
for us to be fully free, pure practical reason must specify at least some of
our final ends as well as setting limits on the means we can use for achieving
them. Whether it must specify all our final ends is a difficult question of
interpretation we’ll discuss later.
. The term “humanity” is appropriate in both the positive and negative
interpretations: in the negative because it is reasonable and rational beings
as possessing humanity that constitute the limits against which we must
not act; in the positive because the obligatory ends are intimately connected
with the good of human persons: more specifically, with cultivation of their
moral and natural perfection and the fulfillment of their proper happiness
(as given by their permissible ends). Once obligatory ends are seen as certain
values associated with human persons, we see the way in which the good
of a (perfected) reasonable and rational person who is happy is an end-initself. In this connection, recall from Gr I:– (–) that moral perfection
(a secure good will) is the supreme form of intrinsic value.
Further, the idea of a positive and a negative interpretation of the second
[ ]
:
formulation is suggested by the fact that there is a natural contrast between
the first and the second pair of examples. In the first pair, the point stressed
is that we are not to treat humanity in ourselves, or in the person of others,
as a mere means to the ends wanted by our natural desires. Whereas in
the second pair of examples, Kant stresses that we must go beyond this
and make our conduct cohere with humanity in our person, that is, we
must promote our greater perfection (moral and natural) and further the
happiness of others. Kant draws an intuitively natural contrast between the
two pairs of examples and uses the words “negative” and “positive” to express the difference. Hence our terminology.
Often Kant states a basic idea of the Groundwork more clearly in a later
work. This comes from the second Critique ::
The moral law is holy (inviolable). Man is indeed unholy enough; but
he must regard humanity in his own person as holy. In all creation
everything he chooses, and over which he has any power, may be used
merely as a means; man alone, and with him every rational creature, is
an end in himself. By virtue of the autonomy of his freedom he is subject
to the moral law, which is holy. Just for this reason every will, even
every person’s own individual will, in relation to itself, is restricted to
the condition of agreement with the autonomy of a reasonable being,
that is to say, that it is not to be subject to any purpose that cannot
accord with a law which might arise from the will of the passive [leidenden] subject itself; the latter is therefore never to be used merely as a
means but itself also at the same time as an end [emphasis on “passive”
(for leidenden) is mine].
This fits the interpretation proposed, since whether a precept of justice
or of virtue might arise from the will of the passive subject is settled by
the CI-procedure.
§. Conclusion: Remarks on Groundwork II:– (–)
. There is a difficulty with the suggested reading of the second formulation
that must be faced. It concerns the fact that the passages II:– (–),
[ ]